domingo, 22 de março de 2015

Thomas A. Szlezák - Reading Plato

Nobody was more conscious than Plato that the reception of philosophy is conditioned by each individual’s limitations. Again and again he makes us experience how an interlocutor is hindered by his own particular mind-set from grasping what is meant.

One of the most famous examples is Callicles in the dialogue, the Gorgias. Callicles represents the thesis of the so-called natural right of the stronger. According to this it is right and proper that the man who is superior to the others in strength and power subjugate them and ruthlessly use them for the furtherance of his own interests. The thesis goes that nature itself desires the dominance of the stronger; the traditional view of justice, which limits the fulfilment of one’s own desires in terms of the rights of others, is nothing other than an ideological construct of the weak by means of which, for their selfprotection, they wish to discredit the strong man’s healthy striving after the uninhibited fulfilment of his instincts and wishes (see Gorgias 482c–486d).

Plato could have had this thesis debated in a calm and disassociated manner as a simply theoretical contribution towards a basic foundation of ethics. Instead, he makes Callicles express it as his own personal belief. It is not just an intellectual ‘position’ but the direct expression of his pathological ambition and his boundless egocentrism. When Socrates demonstrates to him with compelling reasons that the conventional concept of justice makes sense while the so-called right of the stronger is self-contradictory, Callicles can no longer follow Socrates’ reasoning — certainly not, however, out of a lack of intelligence, because he obviously has no little of that, but because of the limitations of his character. It is stated quite openly that it is his unbridled drives which hinder him from understanding and accepting Socrates’ theoretically well founded and morally wholesome view (see Gorgias 513c).

In particular, Callicles has a perverted view of himself: he identifies himself with his desires and instincts (Gorgias 491e–492c). He does not know and does not want to know that human beings are more than their instincts and that reason does not exist in them to be deployed purely instrumentally in the service of their instincts, but is a divine force which exercises control over the lower parts of the soul. Socrates obviously has a corresponding theory of the inner structure of man available as a reply (see Gorgias 493aff.), but when he sees that Callicles would not be able to know what to make of it, he does not even begin to explain it with arguments, but is content to give a few hints which are only understandable in their full range from the fully developed doctrine of the soul in the Republic. Callicles is, however, made aware that he still does not know even the ‘Lesser Mysteries’; but initiation into the ‘Greater Mysteries’ is not permissible without a knowledge of the lower step (497c). Put another way, the real solution of the problem, which for Plato can be produced only by recourse to the inner structure of man, does not need to be imparted to a character like Callicles, since he lacks the personal qualifications for accepting such truths adequately. Thus Callicles receives only an ad hominem refutation as Socrates demonstrates the contradictory nature of his position, on Callicles’ own level of argumentation (494bff).

With this brilliant example of literary characterisation Plato tells us with all clarity that his philosophy demands the whole human being. Intellectual capability alone is insufficient; what is required is an inner relationship between the thing which is to be conveyed and the soul to which it is to be conveyed. Anybody who is not prepared to enter upon a process of inner transformation is not entitled to know the full solution either.